THE PROBLEM OF EVIL:
“Videbam Satanam
sicut fulgor de caelo cadentem.” 1
Exonerating God
By: Geoffrey K. Mondello
(Revised August 17, 2024)
The Problem of Evil
Exonerating God
No
single factor is invoked more often in people turning away from God,
or in their failing to believe in Him, than the occurrence — note that
I do not say the “existence” of evil, especially as it manifests itself
in suffering.
The occurrence — not
the existence — of evil appears incompatible with God, or at least a
coherent conception of God as both — and simultaneously — absolutely
good and absolutely powerful. That God and the occurrence of evil should
coexist appears logically contradictory and ontologically incompatible.
The one is effectively the abrogation of the other. The existence of
God, it is argued, precludes (or ought to preclude) the occurrence of
evil, and the occurrence of evil precludes (or ought to preclude) the
existence of God.
While we can readily
adduce empirical evidence, that is to say, tangible instances, of evil
to discredit the existence of God, the availability of evidence to corroborate
the existence of God, on the other hand, is so exiguous that even when
such instances are invoked, they are deemed extraordinary events in
the affairs of men; indeed, events so far from commonplace that we call
them miraculous — that is to say, inexplicable interventions conditionally
attributed to God in the absence of alternate explanations that may
yet be forthcoming. Whether or not this is a sufficient, if concise,
summary, the general implication is clear: evidence of evil overwhelmingly
exceeds evidence of God. If sheer preponderance is the criterion to
which we appeal, God loses.
Evil comes as a scandal
to the believer who asks, “How can this be, given the existence of God?”
To the disbeliever
no such scandal arises — only scorn for the believer who is left in
perplexity, unable to deny the existence of God on the one hand … while
equally unable to deny the occurrence of evil on the other.
We appear to be consigned
to either nihilistic resignation in the one camp (understanding evil
as somehow ontologically inherent and rampant in the universe
…. although we cannot explain why), or an unreasoned and therefore
untenable affirmation of the existence of God — despite
the contradictory concurrence of evil — in the other.
Both appear to be damned to perplexity.
Neither has satisfactorily
answered the question implicit within every occurrence of evil: “Why?”
The Problem ... and why we must respond to it
Before we begin
our attempt to arrive at an answer to the problem of evil, we must first
clearly summarize and completely understand the nature of the problem
itself.
While this may appear
obvious, all too often our efforts to make sense of the experience of
evil in our lives and in the world fail to adequately address implicit
or unstated premises apart from which no answer is either forthcoming
or possible.
Failing to follow
the premises, we fail to reach a conclusion.
Instead, we reflexively
seize what is incontrovertible (the occurrences of evil) and … understanding
nothing of its antecedents, satisfy ourselves that it is entirely a
mystery — in other words, utterly incomprehensible to us — in fact,
so opaque to our ability to reason it through (which we do not)
that we throw up our hands in either frustration or despair … declaring
that either it is the will of God in a way that we do not understand,
or that there can be no God in light of the enormities that we experience.
In either case — whether
we affirm that God exists despite them, or deny that He exists
because of them — we confront the experience of evil as an impenetrable
mystery. Such a facile answer, I suggest, is not a satisfactory state
of affairs at all.
Antecedents
We
can only speculate upon the pre-Adamic origin of evil.
That evil preceded
the creation of Adam and Eve in the Garden of Paradise is clear.
We are given no
explanation of the genesis of evil as it predated the creation of man.
We only know that it had already manifested itself in the Garden — as
something already extrinsic to it and antagonistic
toward it. That is to say, in the Creation Narrative, we encounter from
the outset the parallel existence of the serpent (a personification
of evil) with man prior to the Fall.
I say parallel
because the serpent possesses a supernatural existence
parallel to and contemporaneous with, the created nature of man, much
in the way that the supernatural being of Angels coexists with the natural
being of men.
While we are unable
to explain evil prior to the creation of man (simply because
no narrative exists to which we can appeal apart from one utterance
of Christ in Saint Luke 10.18: “I saw Satan like lightning falling
from heaven.”), we are not, however, for this reason absolved from
explaining not only how evil came to obtrude upon the affairs of men,
but why it is not incompatible with our conception of God as all-good
and all-powerful.
Philosophy calls this
endeavor a theodicy. We needn’t be intimidated by this, nor think ourselves
unequal to it, as we shall see.
To further compound
the issue, the problem is no mere academic matter from which we can
stand aloof as so many theorists to hypothetical abstractions. It is
a problem that vexes us, and lacerates us at every turn, believer, and
unbeliever alike. It has a direct and painful bearing upon us; it affects
us, afflicts us, and, yes, sometimes crushes us.
Despite the refuge that
the believer has taken in the notion of mystery, or the cynicism to
which the unbeliever consigns himself in hopeless resignation, each
cry out, equally, “Why?” — especially when the evil experienced
or perpetrated is an effrontery to justice or a violation of innocence.
The skeptic…. most often
a casualty of evil…. cannot reconcile the occurrence of evil with the
existence of God. The two appear to be … not just rationally incompatible
… but mutually exclusive. What is more, the empirical evidence of evil
is far more preponderant and far more compelling than any evidence that
can be readily adduced to the existence of God.
The believer, on the
other hand, is painfully perplexed, and sometimes deeply scandalized,
by this seeming incompatibility which often buffets the faith which
alone sustains his belief — the faith that, somehow, the occurrence
of evil and the existence of God are not, in the end, irreconcilable.
First and foremost,
then, it is critical to be clear about the context in which the problem
first occurred, and from which all subsequent instances follow.
Even before this, however,
and as we have said, we must be absolutely clear about the problem itself
which, in summary, follows:
The Problem Summarized:
• We understand
by God an absolutely omniscient Being Who is absolutely good and absolutely
powerful.
• A being deficient
in any of these respects — that is to say, wanting in knowledge, goodness,
or power — we do not understand as God, but as less than God.
• An absolutely
good, absolutely powerful, and absolutely omniscient Being would know
every instance of evil and would neither permit it because He is absolutely
good, or, because He is absolutely powerful, would eradicate it.
• Suffering and
evil, in fact, occur.
• Therefore, God,
from Whom evil cannot be concealed, cannot be absolutely good and absolutely
powerful.
• If absolutely
good, God would eradicate all evil and suffering — but does not, and
therefore, while all-good, He cannot be all-powerful.
• Conversely,
if absolutely powerful, then God could abolish evil and suffering but
does not, and therefore, while all-powerful, He cannot be all good.
• Hence, there
is no God, for by God we understand a Being perfect in goodness and
power.
Until we are perfectly
clear about this, we can go no further. Unless we fully grasp the magnitude
of this problem, we cannot hope to understand the reasons why men either
fail to believe in God or having once believed, no longer do so. The
occurrence, the experience, of evil, as we had said in our opening,
appears as nothing less than a scandal to believers, and the cause of
disbelief in unbelievers.
It need not be so.
For our part, we must
be prepared to follow St. Peter’s exhortation, “being ready always to
satisfy everyone that asks you a reason of that hope which is in you.”
2
Hence, we begin.
The Solution to the Problem of Evil
As mentioned earlier,
any attempt to come to terms with the problem of evil vis-à-vis the
existence of God inevitably entails linguistic and conceptual complexities,
especially in the way of suppressed premises, or unstated assumptions.
It is absolutely essential that these latent features, these uncritically
assumed concepts long-dormant in language, be made manifest.
What really is the problem
of evil, and what really is the nature of God in its simplest formulation?
Can God really be exculpated? …. Can He be exonerated of this ontological
cancer that we call evil? ……And what is the real nature of evil itself?
All too often we are
too facile with our answers through some articulation of faith that
we are not adequately prepared to defend.
Our confrontation with
the problem of evil is the greatest confrontation of all — for it is,
in the end, not only the genesis of all that we suffer but remains the
apocalyptic culmination of all that has been and ever will be.
The Solution Summarized
• The problem
of evil and suffering is a moral problem with existential
consequences that extend to, and are manifested within, the universe
of experience.
• The universe
of moral discourse within the context of which alone a discussion
of the notion of evil is possible …. is not coherent apart from the
notion of volition (the will; specifically, the free will).
• Evil, therefore,
cannot be understood apart from moral agency, especially as it pertains
to man of whom it is predicated as either an agent or
a casualty. That is to say, man either causes evil, is
a casualty of evil, or both.
• An all-good
and all-powerful God would not create man imperfectly. If He chose
to create an imperfect man, He would not be all-good; if He was
unable to do otherwise, He would not be all-powerful.
• Free will
is a perfection in man. If we do not concede that free will is a
perfection, then we cannot not concede … to this concession … which
is to say we cannot hold ourselves free to disagree with it, and deem
this better than to be free to disagree with it,
which is logically untenable.
In a word, if free will
is not a perfection, then it pertains more to the notion of perfection
that the will not be free. However, apart from free will, there is no
universe of moral discourse; nothing meritorious and nothing blameworthy,
no intention, action, or event in the affairs of men that is susceptible
of being construed as either good or evil — and no action is good, and
conversely, none is evil — for there is no evil and no good pertaining
to the actions of men.
• But there is
evil.
• And there is
good.
• What is more,
if I am not free not to love God, then my loving God — or anyone or
anything else, for that matter — is without value, for we do not ascribe
the notion of valuation to that which proceeds of necessity.
That the sum of the
interior angles in any triangle is 180 degrees possesses nothing in
the way of valuation. We do not say that it is good or evil. It is geometrically
necessary.
If we agree that free will is a perfection (that it is better to possess
free will than not to possess it), then in creating man, God would have
deprived man of a perfection in his created nature, had He not
endowed man with free will — a notion that would be inconsistent with
either the goodness or the power of God, or both.
• Eve already
knew … was acquainted with … good … for the Garden of Paradise was replete
with everything good, and devoid of anything evil. Eve experienced no
want, no privation. We must keep this in mind, given our classical
understanding of evil as “a privation of good.”
• Eve chose to
know good and evil.
• Eve, by nature
created good, therefore chose … not to know good, the first term,
with which she was already naturally acquainted … but she chose to
know the second term as well: evil. Eve already knew
good, but she knew nothing of evil, for only good existed in
the Garden of Paradise, and she herself was created good.
• Now, it is not
possible to know evil without (apart from) experiencing
evil, any more than it is to know good without experiencing good. We
cannot know, understand, or comprehend, pain and suffering without
— apart from — experiencing pain and suffering — any more
than we can know, understand, and comprehend the color blue without
apart from experiencing the color blue.
• In choosing
to know evil, therefore, Eve inadvertently, but nevertheless
necessarily and concomitantly, chose to experience the evil
of which she erstwhile knew nothing. It was not the case that Eve was
conscious or cognitive of the deleterious nature of evil (for prior
to Original Sin, as we have said, Eve had only known, experienced, good).
• What is more,
no one chooses what is evil except that they misapprehend it as a good,
for every choice is ineluctably a choosing of a perceived good,
even if the good perceived is intrinsically evil.
• The most evil
act is latently a choice of a good extrinsic to the evil act. Man, only
acts for, and is motivated toward, a perceived good, however spurious
the perception or the perceived good. It is impossible to choose an
intrinsically evil act apart from a perceived extrinsic good motivating
the intrinsically evil act.
Eve’s choice, while
free, was nevertheless instigated through the malice and lie of the
Evil One who deceived Eve that an intrinsic evil — explicitly
prohibited by God — was, in fact, an intrinsic good, which it
was not.
I wish to add that the
susceptibility to being deceived does not derogate from the perfection
of man, for the notion of deception is bound up with the notion of trust,
which is an indefeasible good. The opposite of trust is suspicion which
already, and hence anachronistically, presumes an acquaintance with
evil.
• In choosing
to know evil, Eve’s choice necessitated, precipitated, those conditions
alone through which evil can be experienced, e.g., death, suffering,
illness, pain, etc.
Her choosing to know
evil bi-conditionally entailed the privation of the good, the first
term, through which alone we understand evil, the second term.
Evil instantiates no
esse, no actus essendi, evil has no substance: which is
to say, evil possesses no being of its own apart from the good of which
it is only privative, a negation in part or whole. For this reason,
we see the two terms conjoined in Holy Scripture in, “the tree of knowledge
of good and evil.” The existence of the good, does not, as some
suggest, still less necessarily entail, the experience of evil. Adam
and Eve in the state of natural felicity in the Garden of Paradise knew
good apart from any acquaintance with, or any conception of, evil.
• Evil necessarily
implicates good, but good in no way necessarily implicates evil. The
notion of knowledge by way of contrast and opposition is confined to
relatively few empirical instances and always yields nothing of what
a thing is, only that in contradistinction to what it is not.
To know what a thing
is not tells us nothing of what it is. We do not know the color blue
by its opposition to, its contrast with, or in contradistinction to,
a not-blue, for there is no existent “not-blue.” There are only
other colors we distinguish from blue — but we do so without invoking
the notion of contrast or opposition. I do not know blue as “not-red”
(or, for that matter, through invoking any or all the other colors).
I know blue in the experience of blue only. If there is an “opposite”
of blue, or a corresponding negative to blue, it can only be the absence
of color — not simply another color that is “not-blue,” for in that
case every other color would be the opposite of blue — and the opposite
of every other color as well.
• Once again,
in Eve’s choosing to know evil, she consequently and concomitantly chose
the conditions under which alone such knowledge was possible. Among
the conditions informing such knowledge were death, suffering, pain
— and all that we associate with evil and understand by evil.
• Far from being
culpable, God warned Adam and Eve to avoid, “the tree of knowledge of
good and evil.”
• To argue that
the goodness of God is compromised by His injunction against the plenitude
of knowledge through His forbidding them to eat of the “tree of knowledge
of good and evil” is spurious inasmuch as it holds knowledge,
and not felicity, to be the greatest good possible to man. In
withholding complete knowledge, it is mistakenly argued, God deprived
man of an intrinsic good.
• Felicity, or
complete happiness, not omniscience, or complete knowledge, is man’s
greatest good, and only that which redounds to happiness is good for
man, not that which redounds to knowledge, and the two do not completely
coincide.
• To maintain
that to know evil, suffering, illness, death — and unhappiness — redounds
to man’s happiness is an irreconcilable contradiction. Evil is a privation
of the good; consequently, to choose evil is to choose a privation of
the good, specifically that which vitiates or diminishes the good.
• To maintain,
furthermore, that man can know evil, suffering, illness, and death without
experiencing evil, suffering, illness and death is equally unacceptable.
By this line of reasoning, one whose vision is color-deficient can know
the color purple without ever experiencing the color purple ….. know
what is bitter without experiencing bitterness …. know “hot” without
experiencing hotness. Purple, bitterness, hot — evil, suffering, illness,
death (all that we understand by “evil” are not concepts (in the way,
for example, that a simple binomial equation (1+1=2) is a concept independent
of anything existentially enumerable) but experiences, the knowledge
of which demands the experience and cannot be acquired apart from it
any more than pain can be known apart the experience of pain. Pain,
illness, suffering, death, etc. are in no way inherently, intrinsically
good. No one who has experienced the death of a loved one, the pain
of an injury, or illness of any sort will maintain that such knowledge
acquired through these experiences redounds to their felicity; that
their “knowledge” of any of these evils either promotes or contributes
to their happiness.
• God, then, is
in no way culpable of, nor responsible for, the existence of evil. The
occurrence or experience of evil derogates neither from His goodness,
nor detracts from His power.
• If God is all
good, He would confer the perfection of freedom upon man in Adam and
Eve. If He is all-powerful, He would permit the exercise of this freedom.
• To confer the
perfection of freedom of will upon man does not eo ipso imply
that the exercise of the will necessarily involves a choosing between
the good and the not-good or the less-good, still less a choice between
good and evil. Presumably the exercise of this freedom prior to the
Fall was exercised in choices between things of themselves inherently
good, albeit distinguishable in attributes. The fig and the pear are
equally good in nature, but differing in attributes, and to choose the
one over the other is not to imply that the one is good and the other
not-good or even less-good. The choosing to eat the one and not the
other is a choice among alternative goods.
• Nor is the thing
not chosen “less good” in itself than that which is chosen. It is good
proper to its nature. The pear and the fig are distinctly equally nutritious.
• The notion of
choice is only coherent in the context of right reason. Choice (the
exercise of free will), is never gratuitous but is always in accordance
with reason which alone mediates the choice to a coherent end. What
we choose, we choose to coherent ends. In other words, we choose for
a reason — and not spontaneously or gratuitously. Choices are always
ordered to ends, however disordered the choices themselves may be.
• One does not,
for example, choose as the means to nutrition, a stone rather than a
fig. The choosing of the fig does not imply that the stone is not good.
On the other hand, one does not choose figs to build a house, rather
than stones. This does not imply that the fig is not good. The nature
of the fig redounds to nutrition, while the nature of the stone does
not, and the nature of the stone redounds to building while the nature
of the fig does not. One can still choose to eat stones or to build
with figs, but such choices do not accord with ordered reason, which
of itself is also an intrinsic good.
• Only God can
bring good out of evil He does not will, but nevertheless
permits through having conferred the perfection of freedom upon
man. While God could not have endowed man with this perfection without
simultaneously permitting the consequences necessary and intrinsic to
it, He is not Himself the Author of the evil but of that perfection
in man through which — not of necessity (for man is never compelled
to choose — inasmuch as compulsion by definition abrogates choice)
— man chooses evil and subsequently becomes the agent of it.
• The occurrence
of evil, consequently, is neither inconsistent with nor contrary to
the notion of God as absolutely good and absolutely powerful.
The Scriptural Narrative
as the Logical Antecedent:
1. “And He commanded him, saying: Of
every tree of Paradise thou shalt eat: But of the tree of knowledge
of good and evil, thou shalt not eat. For in what day soever thou shalt
eat of it, thou shalt die the death.” 3
2. “Now the serpent was more subtle than any of the beasts of
the earth which the Lord God had made. And he said to the woman: Why
hath God commanded you, that you should not eat of every tree of paradise?
And the woman answered him, saying: Of the fruit of the trees that are
in paradise we do eat: But of the fruit of the tree which is in the
midst of paradise, God hath commanded us that we should not eat; and
that we should not touch it, lest perhaps we die. And the serpent said
to the woman: No, you shall not die the death. For God doth know that
in what day soever you shall eat thereof, your eyes shall be opened:
and you shall be as Gods, knowing good
and evil.”
4
Concerning the Genesis
of Evil
The argument thus far
articulated is clearly framed within the Biblical context in which it
first presents itself to us, and as such may be understood as a type
of epoche, or bracketed narrative, the authenticity of which
we assume as Catholics — not necessarily apart from discursive reasoning,
but not articulated exclusively or even largely in terms of it, either.
Whatever we can speculate upon regarding the origin of evil, of one
thing only can we be certain: that the origin of evil is radicated in
the will.
If we seek an ontological
genesis of evil, we shall not find one … simply because what we understand
as evil is a privation of being and not constituting, let alone instantiating,
a being itself whose ontology is tautologically reciprocal with
evil.
In the strictest sense,
there is no purely evil being. This is tantamount to saying there is
a being nothing, or, alternately, a nothing being. In a word, it is
an oxymoron.
This is also not to
say that there is no single being, or categories of beings, from which
the good has been exhaustively, but not totally, deprived, and we understand
such beings as evil not in the sense of what they possess in
their being but in the sense of what is deficient in their being:
specifically, the good in whatever measure — and precisely
by that measure — of the absence of good in their being, are they
construed as evil.
In that inverted and
simulative realm of evil, just as there are differing magnitudes of
goodness in the holy, there are differing magnitudes of the absence
of goodness in the evil. As some are to greater or lesser degrees
holy … so, to greater or lesser degrees, are the evil.
The ultimate expression
of this near total privation of the good is personal because it pertains
to a will, and the person in whose will we find this nearly total
extinction of the good we understand as Satan, or the devil.
Apart from a coherent
notion of the will we find nothing to which we
can assign moral predicates, nothing inculpatory or exculpatory, praiseworthy
or blameworthy, no sanctity and no sin; we find no world of moral discourse.
To speculate upon the
root of all evil from the beginning is to speculate upon the
first instance of the corruption of the will. We have no Scriptural
narrative to which we can appeal in answering this and thus no phenomenological
bracket (or epoche) in which to address it as Catholics.
Consequently, every effort will be, at best, conjectural.
We at least know that
it pertained to freedom … specifically freedom of the will … apart from
which there is no moral discussion. We have no narrative through which
we can answer the question of why, in the first instance, Satan
sinned through a willful refusal to cooperate with God.
This has been speculated
upon by theologians throughout history as attributable to pride, specifically
concerning the Incarnation of Jesus Christ in the Immaculate womb of
Mary which instigated the sin of angelic pride: specifically, in Satan’s
refusal to worship God Who became man — in the Person of Jesus
Christ — for we must remember that, in the hierarchy of being, “man
… was created less than the angels”5. The refusal to worship the True God Who became True Man — the
first corrupt act of free will in the created world, was arguably the
primal evil act, the very first instance of evil in the chronology of
creation.
The earliest allusion
to this occurs in the Book of Wisdom: “For God created man incorruptible,
and to the image of His own likeness he made him. But by the envy of
the devil, death came into the world.”7
Thus, while the circumstances
surrounding the first defection of the free will from the supremely
good will of God can only be speculated upon, the free will of Satan
nevertheless is resolved into a causa sui, a cause in and of
itself, originating from no prior cause that could be held to subvert
or attenuate the autonomy of the free will of Satan.
That this primeval malice
obtruded upon the natural world through the equally free agency of the
will of Eve and Adam is, unquestionably, the greatest tragedy in human
history. This, however, is not do indict God for endowing man with free
will, as I have argued. Indeed, understood in the context of the
Felix Culpa, the remedy that we find in salvific history in the
Person of Christ Jesus has immeasurably exceeded in supernatural
felicity what had erstwhile only been endowed with natural felicity
and was subsequently lost through sin.
________________________________________
1
“I saw Satan like lightning
falling from heaven.” (Saint Luke 10.18)
Apart from the diabolical, by whose instigation Eve was
deceived. The provenance of this primeval malice which antecedes the
creation of man is the topic of another subject. Evil was in no way
intrinsic to the Garden of Paradise. Happiness was. The intrusion of
evil upon nature through supernatural artifice only indicates the pre-existence
of supernatural evil apart from nature which was created good. While
chronologically antecedent to nature it was not manifest within it,
even while concurrent with it, for the two — the natural and the supernatural
— are ontologically distinct. The present argument purposes to explain
the origin of evil as it touches upon human existence in nature, not
the provenance of evil as it pertains to diabolical being in the supernatural.
2 1 St. Peter
3.15
3 Genesis
2.16-17
4
Genesis 3.1-5
5
Hebrews 2.7
6
Wisdom 2.23-24
Saturday August 18,
2024
Feast of St. Agapitus, Martyr
___________________________________________
Contributed
by:
Geoffrey K. Mondello
author of
The Metaphysics of Mysticism: A Commentary
Available on
Amazon
Printable PDF File
Totally Faithful to the Sacred
Deposit of Faith entrusted to the Holy See in Rome
“Scio
opera tua ... quia modicum habes virtutem, et servasti verbum
Meum, nec non negasti Nomen Meum”
“I
know your works ... that you have but little power, and
yet you have kept My word, and have not denied My Name.”
(Apocalypse
3.8)
Copyright © 2004 - 2024 Boston Catholic
Journal. All rights reserved. Unless otherwise stated, permission
is granted by the Boston Catholic Journal for the copying
and distribution of the articles and audio files under the
following conditions: No additions, deletions, or
changes are to be made to the text or audio files in any
way, and the copies may not be sold for a profit. In the
reproduction, in any format of any image, graphic, text,
or audio file, attribution must be given to the Boston Catholic
Journal.
|
|